Judaism and Democracy (Part 1 of 2)
STUDENT SUMMARIES OF SICHOT OF THE ROSHEI YESHIVA
SICHA
OF HARAV
Judaism
and Democracy
Part 1 of 2
Adapted by
Dr.
Translated by
My position
concerning the relationship between religion and state was expressed in an
article published decades ago (Religion and State:
The Case for Interaction, Judaism
15, Fall 1966, pp. 387-411; reprinted in Leaves of Faith: The World of Jewish
Living [
This subject
used to be a popular one in our circles. In essence it is immanent to the wider
western society within which we live. The crown of democracy has traditionally
been accorded a fair degree of prestige. There was a period when even
fundamentally totalitarian states such as
The world of
Torah, too, seeks inclusion within the sphere of democracy. This is
understandable not only from the practical, pragmatic view the public
relations perspective. Fundamentally speaking, democratic perception and
thinking include values that are very close to our hearts.
But can we
wholeheartedly claim that we are democratic in the broad, secular sense of the
term? Are we really able to abide by total democracy, in which this value is
supreme? I believe that the answer to this question is in the negative.
We approach
the subject from a dual perspective. On the one hand, there is the
philosophical, theoretical ideal. On the other hand, we must address the
political and social reality in which we find ourselves.
We are not
speaking of a merely theoretical subject. This issue cuts deep; it descends to
the depths of the reality of our lives. If we are talking about constructing a
political system within a framework both ideal and practical that is
characterized by its religious aspect, then the question of the relationship
arises and deepens as the two elements collide in internal conflict.
Our situation
is different from that of most western countries in which the religious and
democratic aspects are more or less balanced. In these countries the matter
underwent debate for many years. There were social and political developments,
and they arrived at some sort of balance in the battle against clericalism,
against the rule of religion, and in the matter of the conflict between religion
and democracy. All of this happened in
Once we
merited, by Gods mercies, to return to the Promised Land, many good minds
deliberated the issue and treated it both from a practical point of view and
from a point of view that sought to clarify our ideological and political
beliefs in this regard. However, our reality is one that is developing and
changing all the time, in contrast with a process that took place over hundreds
of years in other countries and other cultures. Thus, the question is a burning
one both because of our devotion to certain democratic values, and as a result
of our profound connection with society in general, and the society in which we
find ourselves in particular.
I shall not
focus here on the practical, immediate reality, but rather on the more general
perspective. I start with the negative aspect: in one sense it is clear that
there is contradiction and opposition, in moral and philosophical terms, between
democracy as it is perceived by many of its adherents, and our Torah world in
particular, as well as the world of religion in general.
The most
basic foundation of all political science is the question of the source of
authority and its roots: from whence does it derive its values and draw its
power, on the practical level, but also more importantly on the level of
ideas? In this context, it is clear that if we compare our world view to that of
western democracy, there is a contradiction. Democracy maintains that the source
of authority, its root and basis, is the vox populi the voice of the
public. The public decides, for better or worse; the public determines what is
desirable and what is not, both in legal and in moral terms.
We, on the
other hand and I refer also to those who cleave to universal religious values
in general, and to our world-view in particular highlight the idea that the
source of authority is the Holy One and His will. He is our God and there is no
other. We are His servants; we are happy to serve Him, and we proclaim like
any believing Jew that They are My servants, whom I took out of the
At the same
time, however, one thing must be clear. While we differ regarding the roots of
authority, this does not necessarily place us in opposition to the democratic
perception of government, namely, how it is structured and how it is elected.
The contradiction between they are My servants and a view of authority as
emanating from a human, secular power is one that would exist even if we were
speaking of an oligarchy or monarchy.
Thus, even
before we get into the details, we approach questions of society and politics
with a different perspective. Democracy is not more of a threat to religion than
are other forms of human rule. When the nation demands that Shemuel appoint them
a king, this is taken as a rejection of God: It is not you that they reject,
but Me that they reject from ruling over them (I Shemuel 8:7). There is
a conflict here not between democracy and Torah, but rather between human
authority and divine authority. Similarly, the battles between Church and State
in western culture, from the Middle Ages until modern times, were not conducted
against democratic regimes, but rather against monarchic ones.
Our
perspective is that, under all regimes, human commands may not nullify Divine
commands. This is Rambams ruling, in keeping with the Gemara. This is true
concerning a king, and it is also true concerning Congress, or the Knesset. This
question does not pertain specifically to democracy: The words of the Master
and the words of the disciple to whom do we listen?
We may ask
whether the Torah advocates a specific type of government. The Gemara debates
the meaning of the verse, You shall appoint a king over yourself (Devarim
17:15). Many authorities are firmly committed to the view of the Rambam, who
counts the appointment of a king as one of the positive mitzvot; in his
view, this represents not a possibility but rather a normative, obligatory
instruction. Abarbanel disagrees (as do others); his position in this regard
must certainly have been influenced by the vast experience that he gained during
the period of the Renaissance, with all the intrigues that characterized the
royal houses. In his view, the appointment of a king is permissible, but not
obligatory.
In any event,
the question goes beyond whether we accept Rambams ruling on the matter; it
also involves an understanding of the mitzva of appointing a king, on the most
basic level. Rav
You shall
say: Let me appoint a king
(Devarim 17:14) according to our teachers
this is a positive commandment, obligating us to make this declaration
following the inheritance and settlement of the land, similar to the formulation
of [the commandment], You shall make a parapet for your roof (ibid. 22:8),
etc. The Torah specifically uses the expression, you shall say, for it is a
commandment that [the people] come before the kohanim, the leviim, and the
judge, and tell them, We want to appoint a king over us.
In other
words, according to the Ramban the Torah is providing instruction and guidance
for the public that is interested in pursuing this possibility, but the mitzva
to appoint a king is only in response to public demand. Ramban does not address
the question of whether there are circumstances in which the public may refrain
from asking for a king, but the obligation of the kohanim, leviim and the judge
applies only when such a demand exists.
A sharper
question now arises: if, indeed, the public does choose a monarchy, what weight
if any is awarded to public opinion in shaping this royal regime and
determining who stands at its head?
From the
Gemara in Sanhedrin it is clear that, concerning the kings of the ten
tribes (i.e., those not of the Davidic dynasty), the person coronated as king
was chosen by the public. Although he was not called the president or the
prime minister, he was subject to the will of the people and their election.
The Keren
Ora (in his commentary on Horayot 11) goes a step further. He
believes that if the public has had enough of the king, the public is entitled
to remove him immediately and replace him with someone else. This is a rather
revolutionary view, and it certainly reflects so a very democratic perception.
Even if one
were to advocate monarchy and in the future, the dynasty of the House of David
is destined to be reinstated, as part of our vision of the redemption this
still does not mean a kingship that sows fear and rules by tyranny. The monarchy
must certainly be sensitive to the public will, and the public will must be able
to find practical expression.
In this
context, the question is not only whether or not there exists a monarchy, but
also the status of the king, his powers, and the extent of his authority. Some
of his spheres of authority are listed in Sanhedrin, on the basis of the
narrative in Sefer Shemuel, but there is no full answer regarding the
extent to which other individuals or bodies can be part of the political and
national landscape. By choosing a middle path, one may reconcile what could be
perceived as a contradiction between democracy and the Torah world view.
But we should
not suffice with this. The relationship between Halakha and democracy must be
examined not only in terms of reconciling the contradictions. There are
certainly contradictions between Halakha and democracy particularly in the
sphere of the rights of individuals. We must rise above but not ignore these
points of conflict. We may see Halakha not only as facilitating the existence of
democracy, but also in certain senses promoting it, according with it, and
going along with it in the same direction and in the same spirit. [This will be the subject of next
weeks sicha.]
(This speech
was delivered at a conference sponsored by the Zomet Institute in Spring